Main content
Wireless Philosophy
Course: Wireless Philosophy > Unit 4
Lesson 2: Early modern- Early Modern: Locke on Personal Identity, Part 1
- Early Modern: Locke on Personal Identity, Part 2
- Early Modern: Locke on Personal Identity, Part 3
- Early Modern: Descartes' Cogito Argument
- Early Modern: Émilie du Châtelet, Part 1
- Early Modern: Émilie du Châtelet, Part 2
- Early Modern: Margaret Cavendish, Part 1
- Early Modern: Margaret Cavendish, Part 2
© 2023 Khan AcademyTerms of usePrivacy PolicyCookie Notice
Early Modern: Descartes' Cogito Argument
"I think, therefore I am" - almost everyone has heard of René Descartes' famous cogito argument. But what is this argument about? What does it show, and why are so many philosophers excited about it - even today, more than 350 years after Descartes first presented this argument?
Speaker: Dr. Stephan Schmid, Assistant Professor, Humboldt-University.
Speaker: Dr. Stephan Schmid, Assistant Professor, Humboldt-University.
Want to join the conversation?
- Does anyone else have their doubts about this?(7 votes)
- Doubts, probably not, because you either buy into this deep self examination or you don't. I'm willing to accept, as Popeye said, that i yam what i yam. SO I have no doubt that this level of analysis is too deep for me, although interesting to hear. And BTW, Dr. Schmid's presentation, along with the graphics, was quite entertaining.(4 votes)
- I wonder if the question has been addressed, which for me arises at, whether it is a logical jump to the idea that "what is thinking" may arise from the initiation of a biological process, spontaneously arising? The question is: Can we logically be proven to have a body? Perhaps the body comes first, and then thinking "begins", for who remembers their first thought? 9:20
It seems to lead to circular argument; no answer at all. Not enough perspective to answer.
I'm sure I'm not the first to have thought this, anyone have a quick answer?(3 votes) - I don't understand the historical significance of Descartes' argument. As is said in the video, there already were arguments similar to the cogito argument before Descartes posited by Aristotle, St. Augustine, etc so this can't give Descartes argument it's historical worth. The radical doubt also isn't new as far as i know as skepticism has been around since at least the time of Plato. But then there's nothing left which is renewing to the argument, or is it just a power play at the right time in history that moves philosphy from the scholastic point of view where knowledge is to be had by the senses to the modern view where knowledge is far less easy to come by? Thougths?(1 vote)
- The historical significance isn't in the argument per se or even in his skepticism. It is that Descartes changed the discourse to something that resembled more 'classical philosophy.' This change is cultural and historical if you buy that he was writing right as "The Enlightenment" of Europe is taking place. Now this is a typical Western Civilization observation, so it is problematic, but the fact remains that Descartes (revolutionary or not) becomes a major influence of philosophy and thought in the European arena. In short, he becomes a type of segue between the medieval and modern world and Western thought would conceivably be much different now had he not put forth the arguments he did at the time he did. An analogy: Henry Ford did not invent the automobile, however, because of his method of distribution, there is historical significance concerning Henry Ford and the automobile.(5 votes)
- I don't really understand why thinking would prove we really exist. If everything we experience can be an illusion then it doesnt seem too hard to imagine an illusion that is able to emulate thought(2 votes)
- Were Locke and Descartes in agreement with regards to existence? Please feel free to correct or confirm the following line of reasoning. Locke held that consciousness is necessary for "personage". Descartes stated "thinking" is a necessity to prove one's existence. If "thinking" is a subset of consciousness and existence is equivalent to "personage" then Descartes and Locke arrived at the same conclusion using different terminology.(2 votes)
- we are alive and thinking so therefor we are thinking and alive(1 vote)
- Descartes: If something does not exist, it ( that something ) cannot think.
I think, therefore I exist.
corollary is '
A) If something does not exist,
it ( not existing thing ) cannot think.
and,
B) If something exists, it can think.
The stone exists, therefore the stone can think.
My questions:
1) Whether I am right, or do I go wrong? (logically?)
2) Are Perceptions never wrong/deceptive?(1 vote)- B) is incorrect. If something thinks, then it must exist. But just cause something exists doesn't mean it can think.(1 vote)
- In other words, being self-aware and conscious means you can prove to yourself and only yourself that you do in fact exists. So, if you speak to someone else that deems they think, you will never know if they truly exist because you cannot prove whether they in reality do think or not? His theory is really just an endless cycle that will never end.(1 vote)
- what is all about René Descartes method of doubts ?(1 vote)
- A stone exists in my perspective because I have seen it and touched it and so I thought there's the stone. But the stone doesn't exist from its own perspective cos it can't think itself. Is this what Descartes meant?(1 vote)
- I would go as far to say that, just because you can touch the stone? does not mean it exists.(1 vote)
Video transcript
(intro music) Hi, I'm Stephan Schmid. I'm teaching at the Humboldt
University in Berlin in Germany, and today, I want to talk about Descartes's famous cogito argument. Even if you have never heard of the name "cogito argument" before, or of Descartes, you might have encountered
the argument itself. It is nothing other than the
famous philosophical insight "I think, therefore, I am," or in Latin, "cogito ergo sum." This argument has become so popular that it has even become
the subject of jokes. Consider this one. Descartes walks into a bar. The bartender walks up to him and says, "Hey, would you care for a drink?" Descartes replies, "Hmm, I think not." And poof! He disappears. Now, I admit that this
joke is probably not the best joke ever, but
Descartes's cogito argument, to which this joke appeals,
is definitely pretty cool. The most exciting feature of
Descartes's cogito argument is not the argument itself, though. It can actually already be found in Aristotle and Saint Augustine. It is rather the philosophical
question that Descartes tried to answer with it. But who was this guy Descartes, anyway? And what is this question
that the cogito argument is supposed to answer? Rene Descartes was a French
philosopher of the seventeenth century. He was dissatisfied with
the philosophy of his time, which was dominated by
scholastic philosophy. The scholastics saw to
answer highly abstract philosophical questions
mainly on the basis of Aristotle's teaching. Descartes was dissatisfied
with this kind of philosophy because he considered their
highly abstract disputes pointless and futile, and
also unable to accommodate the results of the rising
mechanistic physics, which sought to account
for natural phenomena in mathematical terms. On account of his dissatisfaction
with the philosophy of his day, Descartes came to think that the philosophy was in
need of a fundamental reboot, a completely fresh start. This is surely a nice idea, but how do you build a
new philosophical system? Well, maybe it's just in
a way we usually build new and stable things, such
as houses and monuments: just by building them up on a
strong and stable foundation. Yet, what would serve as an
appropriate firm foundation upon which to build a
new philosophical theory? Descartes was convinced that
nothing could do the job better than our most certain beliefs that is, the things that we
can really be sure are true. Let us now finally turn
to Descartes's attempt to establish a firm foundation
for his new philosophy. He carries out his attempt
most extensively in his "Meditations On First Philosophy." As we said, he wants to
find absolutely certain and unshakable beliefs that he can build his new philosophy upon. The method that Descartes suggests has become known as
"Descartes' radical doubt." The main idea is to
subject all our beliefs to radical doubt, and
then see which of them can withstand such doubt
and hence be accepted as absolutely certain. As the application of this method reveals, there is indeed a huge
difference between the things that we in fact take
ourselves to be certain about and the things we may justifiably do so. Just consider the following examples. You're doubtlessly pretty certain that you're watching a video right now, or that you have brushed
your teeth this morning, or that two plus two equals four. Yet are you really justified
in being so certain? Descartes thinks that after
having employed his method of radical doubt, you will
have to admit that you are not. Indeed, there are only very few beliefs that pass Descartes's
test of radical doubt. Can you be really certain that you are watching a video right now? No, you cannot. After all you could just
as well be dreaming. The same holds about your beliefs that you brushed your teeth this morning. And most shockingly, perhaps,
not even mathematical beliefs escape Descartes's radical doubt, for how can we be sure that two plus two equals four, say? True, we have often convinced ourselves that we get a collection of four objects if we unite two collections
of two objects, but what ensures that we
did not err every time we convinced ourselves of this? Perhaps there is an evil demon,
or a wicked neuroscientist, who constantly manipulates our thoughts by systematically distracting
us when we try to verify our mathematical beliefs. As these considerations show, Descartes's method of radical doubt leaves hardly any belief unaffected. But there is hope. Descartes argues that
there is at least one thing that we cannot doubt and which we can be absolutely certain about. This is the fact that when we doubt, we cannot doubt that we doubt or think, for doubting is just a form of thinking. But when we can be sure that we think, we can be equally sure that
we exist while we are thinking, for if indeed we can be
sure that we are thinking, there has to be something
that does the thinking, and we are the something, you and I. It is, hence, here that we finally arrive at Descartes' famous cogito argument, "I think, therefore, I am." The cogito argument then
assures us of the fact that there is at least one thing that is impossible to doubt and is thus absolutely certain. This is the fact that
we exist while we think. And this is precisely
the unquestionable fact that can figure as the
unshakable and firm foundation which Descartes has been looking for in order to build his new
philosophical system upon. The prospect of building
a whole world view upon the certainly that
we exist while we think must strike you as not very promising. Given that we can only
be certain that we exist while we think, how can
we ever know, as we seem to, that we live on a planet
we share with human beings and other animals and
which orbits the sun. And how can you know that
two plus two equals four, or that you are watching a video? It is indeed a long road
for Descartes to restore our certainly in our common sense beliefs, and many of these beliefs have
to be abandoned along the way. Amongst those are our
commonly accepted beliefs that materials things are really colored or have other sensory
properties like tastes, smells, and sounds. It takes Descartes the whole
rest of his six meditations to walk down this road
and restore our confidence in our beliefs of mathematical truths and the existence of the outer world. It would take us hours to
carefully reenact all the steps. However, in order to get a rough grasp of Descartes's procedure,
it will be worthwhile to reconstruct just one
step that Descartes takes in order to extend the stock of beliefs that we can justifiably be certain about. The method Descartes employs for extending our certain beliefs
consists in squeezing out the certainties he has already arrived at. Actually, we have already
encountered this method, for Descartes's cogito
argument is such a way of squeezing out a certain
belief or idea from another. After all, the cogito
argument is an argument, that is, a transition or an inference from one belief to another. The unshakable belief that
this argument starts out from is the belief that we are
thinking when we are doubting, and we arrive at this
certainty just by observing that whatever we might
doubt, we cannot doubt that we doubt when we doubt. Now, the cogito argument
takes this certainty and squeezes out the new
certainty that we cannot only be sure that we think when we doubt but also that we exist when we think. And it is exactly this
newly gained certainty of our existence which the
cogito argument provides us that Descartes squeezes next. In a famous passage of his
second meditation, he writes, "I am, I exist - that is certain. "But for how long? "For as long as I am thinking. "I am, then, in the strict sense only a thing "that thinks; that is, I
am a mind, or intelligence "or intellect or reason. "But for all that, I am
a thing which is real "and which truly exists. "But what kind of a thing? "As I have just said - a thinking thing." As becomes plain here, Descartes
immediately squeezes out further information about his nature from the certain belief that
he exists while he thinks. As a result, Descartes cannot
only know with certainty that he exists, but also
that he is a thinking thing, a thing capable of thinking. This is still not a lot, though. At this stage, Descartes can
only be ensured of the fact that he is a thinking thing, and it is still an open question
whether he also has a body, as we usually suppose. If you are puzzled now, or even afraid that you cannot know whether
you really have a body, that you really are watching this video, or that you really have brushed
your teeth this morning, the only comfort I can give you is that Descartes at least
thought that it can be proved that we can be certain that we have a body and that our senses, by
and large, assure us of the existence of other
corporeal things, even though they systematically
deceive us about their nature. And this can be proved by further
squeezing out our clear and distinct idea of
ourselves as a thinking thing. If this promise is not
enough to give you comfort, then there is only one
last advice I can give you. Go and get a copy of Descartes's "Meditations On First Philosophy," and start reading his third meditation. Subtitles by the Amara.org community